In welfare economics and social choice theory, a social welfare function—also called a socialordering, ranking, utility, or choicefunction—is a function that ranks a set of social states by their desirability. Each person's preferences are combined in some way to determine which outcome is considered better by society as a whole.[1] It can be seen as mathematically formalizing Rousseau's idea of a general will.
Social choice functions are studied by economists as a way to identify socially-optimal decisions, giving a procedure to rigorously define which of two outcomes should be considered better for society as a whole (e.g. to compare two different possible income distributions).[2] They are also used by democratic governments to choose between several options in elections, based on the preferences of voters; in this context, a social choice function is typically referred to as an electoral system.
The notion of social utility is analogous to the notion of a utility function in consumer choice. However, a social welfare function is different in that it is a mapping of individual utility functions onto a single output, in a way that accounts for the judgments of everyone in a society.
There are two different notions of social welfare used by economists:
Ordinal (or ranked voting) functions only use ordinal information, i.e. whether one choice is better than another.
Cardinal (or rated voting) functions also use cardinal information, i.e. how much better one choice is compared to another.
Arrow's impossibility theorem is a key result on social welfare functions, showing an important difference between social and consumer choice: whereas it is possible to construct a rational (non-self-contradictory) decision procedure for consumers based only on ordinal preferences, it is impossible to do the same in the social choice setting, making any such ordinal decision procedure a second-best.
Terminology and equivalence
Some authors maintain a distinction between three closely-related concepts:
A social choice function selects a single best outcome (a single candidate who wins, or multiple if there happens to be a tie).
A social ordering function lists the candidates, from best to worst.
A social scoring function maps each candidate to a number representing their quality. For example, the standard social scoring function for first-preference plurality is the total number of voters who rank a candidate first.
Every social ordering can be made into a choice function by considering only the highest-ranked outcome. Less obviously, though, every social choice function is also an ordering function. Deleting the best outcome, then finding the new winner, results in a runner-up who is assigned second place. Repeating this process gives a full ranking of all candidates.[3]
Because of this close relationship, the three kinds of functions are often conflated by abuse of terminology.
Example
Consider an instant-runoff election between Top, Center, and Bottom. Top has the most first-preference votes; Bottom has the second-most; and Center (positioned between the two) has the fewest first preferences.
Round 1
Round 2
Top
40
53
Center
26
Eliminated
Bottom
34
47
Under instant-runoff voting, Top is the winner. Center is eliminated in the first round, and their second-preferences are evenly split between Top and Bottom, allowing Top to win.
To find the second-place finisher, we find the winner if Top had not run. In this case, the election is between Center and Bottom.
Runner-up
Round 1
—
Excluded
Center
66
Bottom
34
(Note that the finishing order is not the same as the elimination order for sequential elimination methods: despite being eliminated first, Center is the runner-up in this election.)
In a 1938 article, Abram Bergson introduced the term social welfare function, with the intention "to state in precise form the value judgments required for the derivation of the conditions of maximum economic welfare." The function was real-valued and differentiable. It was specified to describe the society as a whole. Arguments of the function included the quantities of different commodities produced and consumed and of resources used in producing different commodities, including labor.
Necessary general conditions are that at the maximum value of the function:
The marginal "dollar's worth" of welfare is equal for each individual and for each commodity
The marginal "dis-welfare" of each "dollar's worth" of labor is equal for each commodity produced of each labor supplier
The marginal "dollar" cost of each unit of resources is equal to the marginal value productivity for each commodity.
Bergson argued that welfare economics had described a standard of economic efficiency despite dispensing with interpersonally-comparablecardinal utility, the hypothesization of which may merely conceal value judgments, and purely subjective ones at that.
Earlier neoclassical welfare theory, heir to the classical utilitarianism of Bentham, often treated the law of diminishing marginal utility as implying interpersonally comparable utility. Irrespective of such comparability, income or wealth is measurable, and it was commonly inferred that redistributing income from a rich person to a poor person tends to increase total utility (however measured) in the society. But Lionel Robbins (1935, ch. VI) argued that how or how much utilities, as mental events, change relative to each other is not measurable by any empirical test, making them unfalsifiable. Robbins therefore rejected such as incompatible with his own philosophical behaviorism.
Auxiliary specifications enable comparison of different social states by each member of society in preference satisfaction. These help define Pareto efficiency, which holds if all alternatives have been exhausted to put at least one person in a more preferred position with no one put in a less preferred position. Bergson described an "economic welfare increase" (later called a Pareto improvement) as at least one individual moving to a more preferred position with everyone else indifferent. The social welfare function could then be specified in a substantively individualistic sense to derive Pareto efficiency (optimality). Paul Samuelson (2004, p. 26) notes that Bergson's function "could derive Pareto optimality conditions as necessary but not sufficient for defining interpersonal normative equity." Still, Pareto efficiency could also characterize one dimension of a particular social welfare function with distribution of commodities among individuals characterizing another dimension. As Bergson noted, a welfare improvement from the social welfare function could come from the "position of some individuals" improving at the expense of others. That social welfare function could then be described as characterizing an equity dimension.
Samuelson (1947, p. 221) himself stressed the flexibility of the social welfare function to characterize any one ethical belief, Pareto-bound or not, consistent with:
a complete and transitive ranking (an ethically "better", "worse", or "indifferent" ranking) of all social alternatives and
one set out of an infinity of welfare indices and cardinal indicators to characterize the belief.
As Samuelson (1983, p. xxii) notes, Bergson clarified how production and consumption efficiency conditions are distinct from the interpersonal ethical values of the social welfare function.
Samuelson further sharpened that distinction by specifying the welfare function and the possibility function (1947, pp. 243–49). Each has as arguments the set of utility functions for everyone in the society. Each can (and commonly does) incorporate Pareto efficiency. The possibility function also depends on technology and resource restraints. It is written in implicit form, reflecting the feasible locus of utility combinations imposed by the restraints and allowed by Pareto efficiency. At a given point on the possibility function, if the utility of all but one person is determined, the remaining person's utility is determined. The welfare function ranks different hypothetical sets of utility for everyone in the society from ethically lowest on up (with ties permitted), that is, it makes interpersonal comparisons of utility. Welfare maximization then consists of maximizing the welfare function subject to the possibility function as a constraint. The same welfare maximization conditions emerge as in Bergson's analysis.
For a two-person society, there is a graphical depiction of such welfare maximization at the first figure of Bergson–Samuelson social welfare functions. Relative to consumer theory for an individual as to two commodities consumed, there are the following parallels:
The respective hypothetical utilities of the two persons in two-dimensional utility space is analogous to respective quantities of commodities for the two-dimensional commodity space of the indifference-curve surface
The Welfare function is analogous to the indifference-curve map
The Possibility function is analogous to the budget constraint
Two-person welfare maximization at the tangency of the highest Welfare function curve on the Possibility function is analogous to tangency of the highest indifference curve on the budget constraint.
Kenneth Arrow's 1963 book demonstrated the problems with such an approach, though he would not immediately realize this. Along earlier lines, Arrow's version of a social welfare function, also called a 'constitution', maps a set of individual orderings (ordinal utility functions) for everyone in society to a social ordering, which ranks alternative social states (such as which of several candidates should be elected).
Arrow found that contrary to the assertions of Lionel Robbins and other behaviorists, dropping the requirement of real-valued (and thus cardinal) social orderings makes rational or coherent behavior at the social level impossible. This result is now known as Arrow's impossibility theorem. Arrow's theorem shows that it is impossible for an ordinal social welfare function to satisfy a standard axiom of rational behavior, called independence of irrelevant alternatives. This axiom says that changing the value of one outcome should not affect choices that do not involve this outcome. For example, if a customer buys apples because he prefers them to blueberries, telling them that cherries are on sale should not make them buy blueberries instead of apples.
A cardinal social welfare function is a function that takes as input numeric representations of individual utilities (also known as cardinal utility), and returns as output a numeric representation of the collective welfare. The underlying assumption is that individuals utilities can be put on a common scale and compared. Examples of such measures include life expectancy or per capita income.
For the purposes of this section, income is adopted as the measurement of utility.
The form of the social welfare function is intended to express a statement of objectives of a society.
The utilitarian or Benthamite social welfare function measures social welfare as the total or sum of individual utilities:
where is social welfare and is the income of individual among individuals in society. In this case, maximizing the social welfare means maximizing the total income of the people in the society, without regard to how incomes are distributed in society. It does not distinguish between an income transfer from rich to poor and vice versa. If an income transfer from the poor to the rich results in a bigger increase in the utility of the rich than the decrease in the utility of the poor, the society is expected to accept such a transfer, because the total utility of the society has increased as a whole. Alternatively, society's welfare can also be measured under this function by taking the average of individual incomes:
In contrast, the max-min or Rawlsian social welfare function (based on the philosophical work of John Rawls) measures the social welfare of society on the basis of the welfare of the least well-off individual member of society:
Here maximizing societal welfare would mean maximizing the income of the poorest person in society without regard for the income of other individuals.
These two social welfare functions express very different views about how a society would need to be organised in order to maximize welfare, with the first emphasizing total incomes and the second emphasizing the needs of the worst-off. The max-min welfare function can be seen as reflecting an extreme form of uncertainty aversion on the part of society as a whole, since it is concerned only with the worst conditions that a member of society could face.
The average per capita income of a measured group (e.g. nation) is multiplied with where is the Gini index, a relative inequality measure. James E. Foster (1996) proposed to use one of Atkinson's Indexes, which is an entropy measure. Due to the relation between Atkinsons entropy measure and the Theil index, Foster's welfare function also can be computed directly using the Theil-L Index.
The value yielded by this function has a concrete meaning. There are several possible incomes which could be earned by a person, who randomly is selected from a population with an unequal distribution of incomes. This welfare function marks the income, which a randomly selected person is most likely to have. Similar to the median, this income will be smaller than the average per capita income.
Here the Theil-T index is applied. The inverse value yielded by this function has a concrete meaning as well. There are several possible incomes to which a Euro may belong, which is randomly picked from the sum of all unequally distributed incomes. This welfare function marks the income, which a randomly selected Euro most likely belongs to. The inverse value of that function will be larger than the average per capita income.
Axioms of cardinal welfarism
Suppose we are given a preference relationR on utility profiles. R is a weak total order on utility profiles—it can tell us, given any two utility profiles, if they are indifferent or one of them is better than the other. A reasonable preference ordering should satisfy several axioms:[4]: 66–69
1. Monotonicity: if the utility of one individual increases, while all other utilities remain equal, R should strictly prefer the second profile. For example, it should prefer the profile (1, 4, 4, 5) to (1, 2, 4, 5). Such a change is called a Pareto improvement.
2. Symmetry: reordering or relabeling the values in the utility profile should not change the output of R. This axiom formalizes the idea that every person should be treated equally in society. For example, R should be indifferent between (1, 4, 4, 5) and (5, 4, 4, 1), because the only difference is whether
3. Continuity: for every profile v, the set of profiles weakly better than v and the set of profiles weakly worse than v are closed sets.[jargon]
4. Independence of unconcerned agents:R should be independent of individuals whose utilities have not changed. For example, if R prefers (2, 2, 4) to (1, 3, 4), it also prefers (2, 2, 9) to (1, 3, 9); the utility of agent 3 should not affect the comparison between two utility profiles of agents 1 and 2. This property can also be called locality or separability. It allows us to treat allocation problems in a local way, and separate them from the allocation in the rest of society.
Every preference relation with properties 1–4 can be represented as by a function W which is a sum of the form:
where w is a continuous increasing function.
Harsanyi's theorem
Introducing one additional axiom—the nonexistence of Dutch Books, or equivalently that social choice behaves according to the axioms of rational choice—implies that the social choice function must be the utilitarian rule, i.e. the weighting function must be equal to the utility functions of each individual. This result is known as Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem.
Non-utilitarian
By Harsanyi's theorem, any non-utilitarian social choice function will be incoherent; in other words, it will agree to some bets that are unanimously opposed by every member of society. However, it is still possible to establish properties of such functions.
Instead of imposing rational behavior on the social utility function, we can impose a weaker criterion called independence of common scale: the relation between two utility profiles does not change if both of them are multiplied by the same constant. For example, the utility function should not depend on whether we measure incomes in cents or dollars.
If the preference relation has properties 1–5, then the function w must be the isoelastic function:
^Amartya K. Sen, 1970 [1984], Collective Choice and Social Welfare, ch. 3, "Collective Rationality." p. 33, and ch. 3*, "Social Welfare Functions." Description.
^Tresch, Richard W. (2008). Public Sector Economics. New York: PALGRAVE MACMILLAN. p. 67. ISBN978-0-230-52223-7.
_____, 1977. "Reaffirming the Existence of 'Reasonable' Bergson–Samuelson Social Welfare Functions," Economica, N.S., 44(173), p pp. 81–88. Reprinted in (1986) The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson, pp. 47–54.
_____, 1981. "Bergsonian Welfare Economics", in S. Rosefielde (ed.), Economic Welfare and the Economics of Soviet Socialism: Essays in Honor of Abram Bergson, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 223–66. Reprinted in (1986) The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A. Samuelson, pp. 3 –46.
Sen, Amartya K. (1963). "Distribution, Transitivity and Little's Welfare Criteria," Economic Journal, 73(292), pp. 771–78.
_____, 1970 [1984], Collective Choice and Social Welfare(description), ch. 3, "Collective Rationality." ISBN0-444-85127-5
_____ (1982). Choice, Welfare and Measurement, MIT Press. Description and scroll to chapter-preview links.
Kotaro Suzumura (1980). "On Distributional Value Judgments and Piecemeal Welfare Criteria," Economica, 47(186), p pp. 125–39.
_____, 1987, “social welfare function," The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 4, 418–20
Muhtar KentLahirMuhtar A. Kent1952New York City, U.S.A.KebangsaanTurki - AmerikaPendidikanTarsus American College University of Hull Cass Business School of City University, LondonPekerjaanKetua dan CEO The Coca-Cola CompanyOrang tuaNecdet Kent Muhtar Kent (lahir tahun 1952) adalah seorang pebisnis Turki Amerika yang saat ini menjabat sebagai Ketua dan Pejabat Eksekutif Tertinggi (CEO) The Coca-Cola Company. Sebelumnya ia ditunjuk untuk menjabat sebagai Pejabat Operasi Tertinggi perusahaan pada …
Sukma Violetta Wakil Ketua Komisi Yudisial Indonesia 4Masa jabatan26 Februari 2016 – 5 Juli 2018PresidenJoko Widodo PendahuluAbbas SaidPenggantiMaradaman Harahap Informasi pribadiLahir(1964-08-10)10 Agustus 1964Jakarta, IndonesiaSuami/istriArsul Sani[1]Anak3Alma materUniversitas IndonesiaUniversitas NottinghamSunting kotak info • L • B Sukma Violetta, S.H., LL.M. (lahir 10 Agustus 1964) adalah Wakil Ketua Komisi Yudisial sejak tahun 2016 menggantikan Abbas Sa…
The coat of arms of the Noronha family, counts of Linhares (first creation). The coat of arms of the Sousa Coutinho family, counts of Linhares (second creation). Count of Linhares (in Portuguese Conde de Linhares) was a Portuguese title of nobility created by a royal decree of king John III of Portugal dated from May 13, 1532, and granted to Dom António de Noronha, 2nd son of Pedro de Menezes, 1st Marquis of Vila Real. This family went to live in Spain and remained faithful to the Spanish Habsb…
Pengetahuan yang harus dirasakan dalam realitas. Georges Canguilhem (1904–1995) adalah filsuf Prancis abad ke-20 yang menjadi pelopor penggabungan filsafat mengenai konsep, pengetahuan dan rasionalitas. Pemikiran filsafat Cabguilhem berbeda dengan filsafat yang mengkaji tentang indra dan subjek. Filsafat yang dikembangkan oleh Canguilhem memperoleh pengaruh dari Marxisme dan psikoanalisis. Sumbangsih pemikirannya yang utama adalah pendapatnya bahwa solusi utama dari permasalahan yang terjadi d…
Peta menunjukkan lokasi Pambujan Pambujan adalah munisipalitas yang terletak di provinsi Samar Utara, Filipina. Pada tahun 2010, munisipalitas ini memiliki populasi sebesar 31.018 jiwa dan 5.248 rumah tangga. Pembagian wilayah Secara administratif Pambujan terbagi menjadi 26 barangay, yaitu: Cababto-an Cabarian Cagbigajo Canjumadal Doña Anecita Camparanga Geadgawan Ginulgan Giparayan Igot Ynaguingayan Inanahawan Manahao Paninirongan San Ramon Senonogan Don Sixto Tula Sarana pendidikan Sarana pe…
1755 battle of the French and Indian War Battle of the MonongahelaPart of the French and Indian WarWashington the SoldierLt. Col. Washington on horseback during the Battle of the Monongahela – Reǵnier 1834DateJuly 9, 1755[1]Locationnear present-day Braddock, Pennsylvania40°24′13″N 79°52′7″W / 40.40361°N 79.86861°W / 40.40361; -79.86861Result French-Indian victoryBelligerents France New FranceOttawasAbenakiLenni LenapeHuronsPotawatomisOjibwa …
Species of bird Northern slaty antshrike Conservation status Least Concern (IUCN 3.1)[1] Scientific classification Domain: Eukaryota Kingdom: Animalia Phylum: Chordata Class: Aves Order: Passeriformes Family: Thamnophilidae Genus: Thamnophilus Species: T. punctatus Binomial name Thamnophilus punctatus(Shaw, 1809) Synonyms Thamnophilus punctatus punctatus The northern slaty antshrike (Thamnophilus punctatus) is a species of bird in subfamily Thamnophilinae of family Thamnophili…
Type of personal naming custom used in Mongolian culture This article has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these template messages) This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Mongolian name – news · newspapers · books · scholar …
Pour les articles homonymes, voir Chaux. la Chaux Caractéristiques Longueur 11,3 km Bassin collecteur Loire Régime pluvial Cours Source dans la forêt domaniale de Balaty · Localisation Ars-les-Favets · Altitude 580 m · Coordonnées 46° 11′ 45″ N, 2° 46′ 35″ E Confluence l'Œil · Localisation Colombier · Altitude 369 m · Coordonnées 46° 16′ 44″ N, 2° 47′ 19″ E Géographie Pays traversés Franc…
العلاقات الأرجنتينية البنمية الأرجنتين بنما الأرجنتين بنما تعديل مصدري - تعديل العلاقات الأرجنتينية البنمية هي العلاقات الثنائية التي تجمع بين الأرجنتين وبنما.[1][2][3][4][5] مقارنة بين البلدين هذه مقارنة عامة ومرجعية للدولتين: وجه المقارن…
Pour les articles homonymes, voir Andronic. Andronic III Paléologue Empereur byzantin Andronic III Paléologue, miniature du XIVe siècle. Règne Co-empereur : 2 février 1325 - 23 mai 1328 Empereur : 23 mai 1328 - 15 juin 1341 13 ans et 23 jours Période Paléologue Précédé par Andronic II Paléologue Suivi de Jean V Paléologue Biographie Naissance 25 mars 1297 Décès 15 juin 1341 (à 44 ans) Père Michel IX Paléologue Mère Rita d'Arménie Épouse Irène de…
Peltaspermales adalah ordo tumbuhan paku biji[1] yang hidup dari zaman Karbon Akhir ke Jura Awal. Ordo ini mencakup sedikitnya satu famili secara valid, Peltaspermaceae, dari zaman Perem ke Jura Awal. Peltaspermales Periode Karbon Akhir–Jura Awal PreЄ Є O S D C P T J K Pg N Restorasi hidup Lepidopteris, dengan dedaunan Lepidopteris ottonis dan serbuk sari yang menghasilkan mikrosporofil dari Antevsia zeilleri, dari Trias Akhir di Eropa.TaksonomiKerajaanPlantaeSubkerajaanViridiplantae…
Andros Townsend Townsend bermain untuk Watford pada 2011Informasi pribadiNama lengkap Andros Darryl TownsendTanggal lahir 16 Juli 1991 (umur 32)Tempat lahir Chingford, Inggris[1]Tinggi 1,83 m (6 ft 0 in)Posisi bermain Gelandang SayapInformasi klubKlub saat ini Luton TownNomor 30Karier junior2000–2009 Tottenham HotspurKarier senior*Tahun Tim Tampil (Gol)2009–2016 Tottenham Hotspur 50 (3)2009 → Yeovil Town (pinjaman) 10 (1)2009 → Leyton Orient (pinjaman) 22 (2)2…
Monument in Zaragoza Agustina Zaragoza and the HeroinesAgustina Zaragoza y las Heroínas41°39′20″N 0°53′33″W / 41.655553°N 0.892405°W / 41.655553; -0.892405LocationZaragoza, SpainDesignerMariano BenlliureMaterialBronze, stoneOpening date29 October 1908Dedicated toAgustina de Aragón, Mother Rafols, Countess of Bureta, Josefa Amar Borbón, Manuela Sancho, Casta Álvarez and María Agustín Agustina Zaragoza y las Heroínas or the Monument to Agustina …
Questa voce sull'argomento stagioni delle società calcistiche italiane è solo un abbozzo. Contribuisci a migliorarla secondo le convenzioni di Wikipedia. Segui i suggerimenti del progetto di riferimento. Voce principale: Internapoli Football Club. Internapoli Football ClubStagione 1970-1971Sport calcio Squadra Internapoli Allenatore Oscar Montez poi Ennio Fabbri Presidente Giovanni Proto Serie C20º posto nel girone C. Retrocesso in Serie D. Maggiori presenzeCampionato: Brilla (38) M…
Voce principale: Prima Divisione 1950-1951. La Prima Divisione fu il massimo campionato regionale di calcio disputato in Liguria nella stagione 1950-1951. Indice 1 Girone A 1.1 Squadre Partecipanti 1.2 Classifica finale 2 Girone B 2.1 Squadre partecipanti girone B1 2.2 Classifica finale 2.3 Squadre partecipanti girone B2 2.4 Classifica finale 2.5 Spareggio qualificazione 3 Girone C 3.1 Squadre partecipanti 3.2 Classifica finale 4 Finali per il titolo 4.1 Classifica finale 4.2 Risultati 4.2.1 Cal…
2002 single by P. Diddy I Need a Girl (Part One)Single by P. Diddy featuring Usher and Loonfrom the album We Invented the Remix ReleasedFebruary 25, 2002 (2002-02-25)Length4:26LabelBad BoyAristaSongwriter(s)Sean CombsChauncey HawkinsMario WinansMichael Carlos JonesAdonis ShropshireJack KnightProducer(s)Mario WinansDiddyP. Diddy singles chronology Pass the Courvoisier, Part II (2002) I Need a Girl (Part One) (2002) I Need a Girl (Part Two) (2002) Usher singles chronology U …
Questa voce sull'argomento film drammatici è solo un abbozzo. Contribuisci a migliorarla secondo le convenzioni di Wikipedia. Al di là della vitaTom Sizemore e Nicolas Cage in una scena del filmTitolo originaleBringing Out the Dead Lingua originaleinglese, spagnolo Paese di produzioneStati Uniti d'America Anno1999 Durata121 min Rapporto2,35:1 Generedrammatico RegiaMartin Scorsese SoggettoJoe Connelly (dal romanzo Bringing Out the Dead) SceneggiaturaPaul Schrader ProduttoreBarbara De Fina,…
Arusukmono Indra Sucahyo Wasekjen PPAL Informasi pribadiLahir10 November 1962 (umur 61) IndonesiaKebangsaan IndonesiaAlma materAkademi Angkatan Laut (1985)Karier militerPihak IndonesiaDinas/cabang TNI Angkatan LautMasa dinas1985–2020Pangkat Laksamana Muda TNISatuanKorps PelautSunting kotak info • L • B Laksamana Muda TNI (Purn.) Arusukmono Indra Sucahyo, S.E., M.M. (lahir 10 November 1962) adalah seorang Purnawirawan TNI-AL yang sekarang menjabat sebagai Wasekjen P…
Pour les articles homonymes, voir Kraft. Kraftwerk Kraftwerk en concert au festival Rock en Seine, à Saint-Cloud, en août 2022.Informations générales Pays d'origine Allemagne Genre musical Musique électronique[1], synthpop[2],[3], avant-garde[4], krautrock[5] (débuts) Années actives Depuis 1970 Labels Kling Klang, EMI Site officiel www.kraftwerk.com Composition du groupe Membres Ralf HütterFritz HilpertHenning SchmitzFalk Grieffenhagen Anciens membres Florian Schneider-Esleben (†)Karl …